Creativity, the Turing Test, and the (Better) Lovelace Test

  • Authors:
  • Selmer Bringsjord;Paul Bello;David Ferrucci

  • Affiliations:
  • The Minds &/ Machines Laboratory, Department of Philosophy, Psychology &/ Cognitive Science, Department of Computer Science, Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI), Troy, NY 12180, USA/ E-ma ...;The Minds &/ Machines Laboratory, Department of Philosophy, Psychology &/ Cognitive Science, Department of Computer Science, Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI), Troy, NY 12180, USA/ E-ma ...;T.J. Watson Research Center, Yorktown Heights, NY 10598, USA/ E-mail: ferrucci@us.ibm.com

  • Venue:
  • Minds and Machines
  • Year:
  • 2001

Quantified Score

Hi-index 0.00

Visualization

Abstract

The Turing Test (TT) is claimed by many to be a way to test for the presence, in computers, of such ``deep'' phenomena as thought and consciousness. Unfortunately, attempts to build computational systems able to pass TT (or at least restricted versions of this test) have devolved into shallow symbol manipulation designed to, by hook or by crook, trick. The human creators of such systems know all too well that they have merely tried to fool those people who interact with their systems into believing that these systems really have minds. And the problem is fundamental: the structure of the TT is such as to cultivate tricksters. A better test is one that insists on a certain restrictive epistemic relation between an artificial agent (or system) A, its output o, and the human architect H of A – a relation which, roughly speaking, obtains when H cannot account for how A produced o. We call this test the ``Lovelace Test'' in honor of Lady Lovelace, who believed that only when computers originate things should they be believed to have minds.